A New Goffman
- Robert W. Fuller’s Politics of Dignity
Thomas J. Scheff
Introduction
The purpose of this chapter is to compare ‘facework’,
a central theme in Erving Goffman’s writings, and Robert W. Fuller’s version of
the same idea. Fuller’s approach covers much the same ground as Goffman but is
interdisciplinary, much clearer and is equally applicable to social interaction
and social structure. Particularly unlike Goffman, Fuller proposes applications
to the real world.
Erving Goffman’s work is
extraordinarily vital and important, but also an enigma. His work is complex,
yet he seldom states an explicit thesis. When he does, the thesis offered is
often misleading. How could that be? Vastly creative people seem to have two
different sides, the creative giant and a much more conventional person,
especially when it comes to assessing their own work. It has been suggested that
Miguel de Cervantes was far from understanding his own masterpiece, Don Quixote. In the course of the argument,
Simon Leys in a review goes on to make a more general point:
The closer a book comes to being a genuine work of
art, a true creation fully alive with a life of its own, the less likely it is
that the author had a full control and a clear understanding of what he wrote.
D. H. Lawrence … summed this up …: ‘Never trust the artist. Trust the tale. The
proper function of a critic is to save the tale from the artist who created it’
(Leys 1998. p. 32).
Although Simon
Leys and D. H. Lawrence were here referring to literature, their point also applies
to academic scholarship. The most creative work does not arise entirely from calculated
effort, but has a major intuitive component. In contemporary language, it comes
from the right brain, light years more complex and original than the calculating
left brain. The creative writer may be a mere channel for work that he or she does
not fully understand. Can we save Goffman’s work from Goffman? In what follows,
this question will be approached. Moreover, I will present Fuller’s perspective
as an extension of and supplement to Goffman’s ideas on facework. The latter
part of this chapter will propose how Fuller’ work shares some of Goffman’s
strengths while avoiding some of his weaknesses.
The Two Goffmans
Erving Goffman’s scholarship is extraordinarily
brilliant, but his pronouncements on its meaning are unreliable. Despite his
freewheeling writing style, or perhaps because of it, he insists that his work
is highly specialized and technical, like any conventional academic effort. His
specialization, he claims, takes three different forms. First, his approach is sociological rather than
psychological. He calls it ‘dramaturgic’, concerning only the socially scripted
parts of the human drama rather than the actors.
His second specification is
closely related: his field of study
is social interaction rather than the individual, on the one hand, or social
structure, on the other. Both specifications align him with conventional rather
than revolutionary scholarship. Like most scholars, he claims loyalty to a
discipline and to a special conceptual approach: dramaturgy.
Finally, Goffman insisted
that his interests are scholarly, not aimed at practical application. This particular claim, unlike the other two, seems quite
accurate. He wanted his scholarship to be pure in this respect, without the
possible taint of attempting to apply it. As he wrote in several different
ways, he saw his job as observing rather than changing the world.
With regard to his first
claim, it is true that Goffman’s writing is more concerned with social
interaction than social structure. Yet, some of his books and articles involve
both. Asylums (1961), for example,
and his articles on mental illness imply many features of the social
institution of mental illness without claiming to do so. Some of his later
work, such as Gender Advertisements
(1979), does not involve social interaction at all, but blatantly concerns only
the institution of female gender implied by commercial ads.
Goffman’s claim that all of
his work is purely dramaturgic is also misleading. In this vein, his best known
book, The Presentation of Self in
Everyday Life (1959), has a split personality. The early chapters outline and
illustrate his dramaturgic approach: a sociology of outer behaviour. But the
middle section, ending with the lengthy Chapter 6 on ‘impression management’,
is mostly concerned with the inner life. Surprisingly, the last chapter returns
to dramaturgy with no mention of the inner battles described and profusely
illustrated in the middle of the book. The right hand knowth not what the left
hand doeth.
In his considerable writings
on face and facework, perhaps his central theme, Goffman’s ‘Everyperson’ is
virtually always struggling to manage the impressions others have of her or him
in order to maintain face. When management fails, as it often does, the
‘Everyperson’ may resort to emotion management, trying to avoid the pain of
embarrassment. In Goffman’s analysis of facework, the individual’s internal
struggles share the stage with the social interaction in which they are
embedded. Here is one of many examples:
Knowing that his audiences are capable of forming bad
impressions of him [1], the individual may come to feel ashamed [2] of a
well-intentioned honest act merely because the context of its performance
provides false impressions that are bad. Feeling this unwarranted shame, he may
feel that his feelings can be seen [3]; feeling that he is thus seen, he may
feel that his appearance confirms [4] these false conclusions concerning him.
He may then add to the precariousness of his position by engaging in just those
defensive manoeuvres that he would employ were he really guilty. In this way it
is possible for all of us to become fleetingly for ourselves the worst person
we can imagine that others might imagine us to be (Goffman 1959:236; numbering
added).
This excerpt mainly concerns a sequence of internal events,
spelling out four moment-by-moment
thoughts and feelings. As it happens, this example, and many others in Goffman’s
work, are the concrete instances of the ‘looking-glass self’ process that Charles
Horton Cooley (1902) failed to supply. Unlike Goffman, Cooley’s emphasis was
entirely on the inner life. However, as already indicated, there are many
limitations to Goffman’s work, especially in the area of application to the individual
and social structure (see Scheff 2005).
Goffman’s World: Its Strengths and Limitations
In his work, Goffman used the word ‘face’ in the sense
of ‘saving face’ and ‘losing face’, vernacular phrases. Like most ordinary
usages that refer to social and emotional process, these phrases involve a
simple physical metaphor applied to a complex situation. Goffman went on to
invent a new word based on these phrases: ‘facework’. The use of new words like
facework, and the use of vernacular words like face in a new way is very
characteristic of Goffman’s overall approach to social science. What are the
advantages and disadvantages of his approach?
After introducing the new
concept of facework, Goffman went on to invent various aspects of face and
facework. As John Lofland (1980:29) has pointed out, the first three pages of
Goffman’s article on facework proposes:
3 types of face
4 consequences of
being out of or in the wrong face
2 basic kinds of
face work
5 kinds of
avoidance processes
3 phases of the
corrective process
5 ways an
offering can be accepted
Although Lofland’s
comments about the idea of facework are highly appreciative, he is at a loss to
understand the meaning of these 22 further items, since no further use is made of
them in the article or in Goffman’s subsequent work.
Goffman
started afresh in each book, not only not explicitly relating his new ideas to
his old ones, but not even taking note of them. This practice gives rise to
some confusion as to Goffman’s intent. How is his approach useful and what are
its limitations?
Goffman’s Main
Strengths
Goffman’s work encompassed and exposed three major strengths: First, it
provided a new vocabulary: Goffman
was an incredibly perceptive observer of the microworld of social interaction.
He created a vocabulary for uncovering this world, otherwise virtually
invisible in modern societies. Second, it was concerned with emotions: most of Goffman’s descriptions
of interaction represented or at least implied emotions as well as thought and
action. In this respect, they were three-dimensional, arousing the reader’s
emotions, sympathy and understanding. This approach remedies a great failing of
most current social science, which tends to be two-dimensional because it
leaves out emotions. Third, his work contributed to trope-clearing: the trope (dominant metaphor) that he most often
attacked was the Western conception of the self as an isolated, self-contained
individual. He offered an alternative conception: the self as an aspect of
social and cultural arrangements. His attack on individualism is one example of
his deconstruction of basic tropes in our society: mental illness, gender,
language and many of the conventions of current social science. His
trope-clearing is highly dramatic and entertaining, but it also exaggerates his
case (see also Scheff 2006:15-32).
Goffman’s deconstructions made his work controversial,
but also give it revolutionary potential. He followed the tradition of Alfred
North Whitehead, Arthur Koestler, Alfred Schutz and Karl Mannheim in order to
create a new social science culture. In this respect, I propose that his work
might serve as a model not only for the study of his field, the interaction
order, but for all of social science. Goffman dealt with primitive conceptual tasks,
preliminary to theory, method and evidence that clear the way for social
science.
1. A Vocabulary for the Microworld
Goffman’s first gift, widely agreed upon by
commentators, is that he was an incredibly perceptive observer of the microworld
of social interaction. He saw and called our attention to a world that
surrounds us, but one that we usually do not notice. Goffman, however, noticed
the riches of activity in the microworld, and invented a panoply of terms and
phrases to describe them. Certainly the idea of facework is one such invention.
Also frequently quoted: impression management, situational improprieties, the
interaction order, cooling the mark, frames (in the special sense in which
Goffman used the term), role distance, alienation from interaction, footing,
and many others. These terms have come to be irreplaceable for those who want
to understand mundane experience in everyday life.
2. Emotions in the Microworld
There is a second
feature of Goffman’s work that is less obvious: unlike most social scientists,
he often included emotions as well as thoughts and action in descriptions of
his actors. However, this feature is more difficult to establish than the first
one. An immediate sticking point is that most of Goffman’s explicit treatment
of emotions mainly concerns one emotion, namely embarrassment. This emotion
plays a central part in his studies, especially the earlier ones, both
explicitly, and in much larger scope, by implication. But why only one emotion?
What about other primary emotions, such as love, fear, anger, grief, and so on?
To the average reader, the virtually exclusive focus on embarrassment seems
arbitrary.
Explicitly,
Goffman gave only one justification. He argued that embarrassment had universal,
pancultural importance in social interaction:
Face-to-face
interaction in any culture seems to require just those capacities that
flustering seems to destroy. Therefore, events which lead to embarrassment and
the methods for avoiding and dispelling it may provide a cross-cultural
framework of sociological analysis (Goffman 1956:266).
Beyond these
considerations, there is another, broader one that is implied in Goffman’s
ideas, particularly the ideas of facework and impression management. Most of
his work implies that every actor is extraordinarily sensitive to the exact
amount of deference he or she is
receiving from others. Even a slight difference between what is expected and
what is received, whether the difference is too little or too much, can cause
embarrassment and other painful emotions.
In an
earlier article, I followed Goffman’s lead by proposing that embarrassment and
shame are primarily social emotions, because they usually arise from a threat
to the bond, no matter how slight or
imaginary. In my view, the degree of social connectedness, of accurately
taking the viewpoint of the other, is the key component of social bonds (Scheff
2000).
A
discrepancy in the amount of deference conveys or at least can be taken to
imply judgement, and so is
experienced as a threat to the bond. The discrepancy may even be completely
imaginary, but it still gives rise to embarrassment. Other emotions such as
grief, fear, anger, guilt and so on also figure in interaction, but not
continuously. Since the perception of even a slight discrepancy, real or
unreal, in deference is automatically sensed, embarrassment or the anticipation
of embarrassment would be a virtually continuous
presence in interaction.
In most of
his writing, Goffman’s ‘Everyperson’ was constantly aware of her or his own
standing in the eyes of others, implying almost continuous states of
self-conscious emotions: embarrassment, shame, humiliation, and in rare
instances, pride, or anticipation of these states. Their sensitivity to the
eyes of others makes Goffman’s actors seem three-dimensional, since they embody
not only thought and behaviour, but also feeling (‘hand, mind, and heart’).
3a. Deconstructing the Self
Goffman’s basic method was to deconstruct the assumptive reality of our society. The most prominent example of
this method was his attack on the social institution of the self-contained
individual. This institution was also repeatedly challenged by Norbert Elias
throughout his writings, but especially in his essay on ‘homo clausus’ (the
myth of the closed, self-contained individual) is this evident (Elias 1998). Sociological
social psychology, in so far as it is derived from the work of George Herbert
Mead (1934), also challenges this conception. Herbert Blumer (1986) was
particularly forceful in this regard.
Goffman’s challenged any perspective that isolates individuals
from the social matrix in which they function. This challenge was not limited
to psychiatry and medicine – its most obvious targets – it pervades virtually
all of his writing. Although Goffman allowed some freedom to the individual
through ‘role distance’, his basic theme was that the self was more or less an
image cast by social arrangements:
The
self … is not an organic thing that has a specific location, whose fundamental
fate is to be born, to mature and die; it is a dramatic effect arising
diffusely from a scene that is presented (Goffman 1959:252-253).
The
self … can be seen as something that resides in the arrangements prevailing in
a social system for its members. The self in this sense is not a property of
the persons to whom it is attributed, but dwells rather in the pattern of
social control that is exerted in connection with the person by himself and
those around him. This special kind of institutional arrangement does not so
much support the self as constitute it (Goffman 1961:168).
The
proper study of interaction is not the individual and his psychology, but
rather the syntactical relations among acts of different persons mutually
present to one another … not, then, men and their moments. Rather, moments and
their men (Goffman 1967:3).
This last passage, because of
its inclusion of the idea that the social scene involves persons mutually present for one another, invokes the
kind of social sharing of consciousness central to Goffman’s focus on
embarrassment described above. The idea of selves arising out of the social
sharing of consciousness had been presaged by literary masters, such as Henry
James and Virginia Woolf. In the words of Joyce Carol Oats: “[James and
Woolf’s] … basic assumption [was] that the individual’s identity is gained only
through participation in a complex field of other individuals’ consciousnesses”
(Oats 1974:33).
3b. Deconstructing Social Reality
There is yet another,
broader dimension to Goffman’s legacy, one at the most elemental level. I
propose that the central thrust of Goffman’s method was toward creating
free-floating intelligence in social science. Although Goffman himself made no
such claim, his work sought to demonstrate, each time anew, the possibility of
overthrowing cultural assumptions about the nature of reality.
Goffman’s primary goal may have been the development of a reflexive
social science. Most of the appreciative reviews of Goffman’s work invoke the
idea of reflexiveness, but only in passing. These commentators do little to
explain what they mean by the term, nor do they explain its implications for
current social science. Was Goffman attempting a reflexive sociology, one that
would create a new culture for social science?
Goffman never clearly explained the overall point of his studies. His
descriptions of the meaning of his work were almost comically laconic. He as
well as others have clearly made the point that he was trying to achieve ‘perspective
by incongruity’. To find more substantial ground, one needs to look at some of
his statements about actors in general. In one of his early statements he said
that “any accurately improper move can poke through the thin sleeve of
immediate reality” (Goffman 1961a, p. 81). Although this passage is not
self-referential, it could also be applied to Goffman’s own basic method, if we
can understand what he meant by an ‘accurately improper move’ and ‘the thin
sleeve of immediate reality’. The meaning of an improper move is easy; one that
violates the assumptions of one’s audience. The idea of improper moves that are
accurate is harder to pin down. The philosopher of science Alfred North Whitehead
wrote:
A
clash of doctrines is not a disaster – it is an opportunity … In formal logic,
a contradiction is the signal of a defeat; but in the evolution of real
knowledge it marks the first step in progress toward a victory (Whitehead 1962:266-267).
Goffman’s method of investigation was to engineer a continuing clash
between the taken-for-granted assumptions in our society and his incongruous
metaphors and propositions. Most improper moves merely embarrass the actor
and/or those near her. But by framing a viewpoint that exactly contradicts
commonly held assumptions, Goffman was developing what Arthur Koestler (1967)
called bisociation – seeing phenomena
simultaneously from two contradictory viewpoints. Like Whitehead, Koestler
thought that all creativity arose from the collision of such contradictory
viewpoints.
Devising a phrase or sentence that is ‘accurately
improper’ in this sense would seem to be a formidable task. One must first hit
upon an important commonly held assumption, then exactly counter it with an
equally plausible assumption. It would depend, like writing poetry, on deep
intuition rather than logical analysis. Goffman was awash with this kind of
intuition.
Goffman’s idea of ‘alienation from interaction’
similarly helps explain what he meant by an improper move. Once again, he did
little to apply this idea to his own work. What he meant was that those actors
who behave improperly, breaking the rules, not only become alienated from
whatever transaction they are involved in, but also might catch an enlightening
glimpse of the nature of that transaction, that is, a glimpse of another
reality behind the conventional one. Peter K. Manning, in passing, makes a
similar point:
His
[technique] is not simply a matter of convenience or artifice. It would appear
to be a deliberate choice of weapons by which to assail the fictional facades
that constitute the assumptive reality of conventional society (Manning
1980:263).
Goffman seems to have been trying to free himself and his readers from
the culturally induced reality in which he and they were entrapped, by making ‘accurately
improper’ moves.
Moreover, the idea of an assumptive reality is a necessity for appreciating Goffman’s
approach. This phrase stands for the total perspective on what is real that is
held in common in each society. As it happens, there is no generally agreed
upon term for this perspective. Émile Durkheim’s usage, ‘collective
consciousness’, comes close, but it seems to leave out the collective
unconscious, and it does not give enough emphasis on the substantive content.
Similarly, the term used by mystics, ‘the great cloud of unknowing’ is
evocative, but it is also partial. It leaves out the ‘knowing’ part of
assumptive realities.
Pace postmodernity, one can never be completely free of
cultural perspectives. There is no place to stand that does not require linguistic
and cultural assumptions. Karl Mannheim’s (1951) point about ‘free-floating
intellectuals’ was that they were not completely free, but free relative to the
attitude of everyday life, which is completely entrapped, like the great
majority of the members of any society. Being able to see any phenomena from
more than one perspective is a great advantage for innovators of any kind, but
it is also fairly rare. Goffman seemed to have achieved sufficient velocity to
escape from some parts of the assumptive world of our society. Following in
Goffman’s footsteps, Robert W. Fuller offers a further avenue for escaping
from, and therefore better understanding, the world of everyday life.
The Struggle for Dignity
Robert W. Fuller’s approach to what he
calls ‘rankism’ and to dignity may be a first step toward a language equally
applicable to individuals and to social relationships. It is based on two fundamental
dichotomies: dignity-humiliation, and legitimate versus abusive use of rank,
i.e. ‘rankism’ (Fuller 2003, 2006; Fuller and Gerloff 2008). Evelin G. Lindner’s
work (2006) is also based on the dignity-humiliation dichotomy but does not
include the concept of rankism. As will be discussed below, some such concept
is needed in order to distinguish between true and false solidarity.
Fuller cites Erving Goffman
dutifully in his first book (Fuller 2003:161). Even though his analysis of
dignity and humiliation is exactly parallel to Goffman’s analysis of facework,
my sense is that Fuller arrived at his approach independently of Goffman. Fuller’s analysis of whether or not dignity is maintained
or lost parallels Goffman’s impression management and Fuller’s humiliation is
equivalent to Goffman’s embarrassment.
Fuller’s
analysis begins with the subjective feeling of being either a ‘Nobody’ or a ‘Somebody’.
Surely, this idea arose because of the extraordinary path that his own life
took. During what can be identified as his first career, he rose through the
ranks from a ‘Nobody’ to a ‘Somebody’: beginning as a physicist at University
of Columbia, then moving to Dean of the Faculty at Trinity College, and then
becoming president of his alma mater, Oberlin College. During his stint as an
educator, which spanned the tumultuous years of the late 1960s and early 1970s,
Fuller’s interests shifted from physics to issues of social justice.
After leaving
Oberlin, he found a role for himself as an unaffiliated, citizen diplomat
during the Cold War, and ended as Chair of the Board of the global organization
Internews, which fosters free and independent media in emerging democracies. With
the collapse of the Soviet Union, Fuller looked back reflectively on his career
and understood that he had been, at different junctures in his life, a ‘Somebody’
and a ‘Nobody’. He thought that in less extreme forms, these kinds of gyrations
might be common to many. His periodic sojourns into ‘Nobodyland’ led him to
consider social relationships both in the small and the large.
For example, in intimate
relations, falling in and out of favour with our nearest and dearest might be a
similar experience (see Fuller’s treatment of parent-child relationships in
Fuller 2003:110-113). At times these shifts are obvious, but often they can be
based only on subtle changes in mood and gesture. Fuller’s first book Somebodies and Nobodies (2003) begins
with the basic idea that we all move back and forth between ‘Somebody’ and ‘Nobody’
feelings, up, down, and around.
Fuller’s second step is to
name the more general feelings that are associated with those specific to ‘somebodiness’
or ‘nobodiness’: dignity goes with feeling like a ‘Somebody’, humiliation with
feeling like a ‘Nobody’. As already indicated, this step is exactly parallel to
Goffman: saving face maintains one’s dignity, while losing it can lead to
humiliation. Goffman’s and Fuller’s ‘Everyperson’ is in a constant struggle to
maintain her or his face/dignity, but impression management often fails,
leading to embarrassment or humiliation. Both authors allow that one can also
manage impressions not only for one’s own sake, but also for the sake of the
dignity of others. This proviso turns out to be important in practical
application to the politics of dignity.
The next and final step in
Fuller’s model is the distinction he makes between ‘rank’ and ‘rankism’. ‘Rankism’
does not concern rank per se, only the
abuse of rank. Some systems of rank are inherently arbitrary and therefore
abusive, e.g. white over black, male over female, hetero over homosexual,
Christian over Muslim, one nation over another, and so on. But even legitimate
systems, such as those in organizations, are often abusive; if not in principle,
then in practice. Rankism is ‘pulling rank’ rather that being fair and
appropriately respectful.
One of the main advantages
of Fuller’s approach – compared to Goffman’s – is that it provides a
distinctively sociological solution to the problem of inequality. That is, it
does not concern economic rank or political hierarchy directly, but dignity and
its opposite, humiliation. The idea of the legitimate and abusive use of rank
also turns out to be important for distinguishing two different types of
feeling ‘Somebody’, a true and a false solidarity. This distinction, as will be
suggested below, may help solve a problem that probably cannot be understood in
strictly economic or political terms: gratuitous and/or interminable conflict.
Fuller and Pamela A. Gerloff’s
(2008) analysis of inequality begins with what they call ‘micro-inequalities’,
the withholding of dignity by one person from another. At work, if the boss
continually interrupts conversations with you to take phone calls, it is a
slight, a small indignity. But such slights add up, even if they are quite subtle.
If they happen often enough, one might feel like a ‘Nobody’. The boss may not
intend it, but to be frequently slighted is humiliating.
Goffman was mainly concerned
only with face-to-face interaction, but Fuller extends the dignity/humiliation
process up to the traditional problem of macro-inequalities between groups. All
contacts between persons and between groups have an effect on the bond: it is either
maintained, strengthened or disrupted. Helping the other person or group
maintain their dignity maintains the existing bond or strengthens it. Rankism
disrupts it. There are no exceptions:
contact cannot occur without affecting the bond. Secure bonds lead to
cooperation, disrupted ones to conflict. When the bond is entirely broken by
rankism, as is often the case, others, even vast groups, can become mere
objects.
Fuller’s approach is
powerful in several different ways. It is applicable to many ostensibly
different fields: race, inter-ethnic and inter-nation relations, gender, sexual
orientation, social class and so on. Rankism is the general term for many different
kinds of abuse.
Fuller’s approach also
implies a theory that may explain gratuitous and/or interminable conflict
between individuals and between groups. For example, the Serbian attack on the
Moslems in Bosnia
in the 1990s can be traced back to a defeat of the Serbs by Moslem Turks
hundreds of years earlier. The Serbs took this ancient defeat as a humiliation
and harboured vengeance until it became possible. Similarly,
France plotted for many years to regain their honour (read dignity) after
defeat in the Franco-Prussian War in 1871, and Adolf Hitler won over the German
people by promising to regain the honour they lost in the defeat in 1918
(Lindner 2006; Scheff 1994). Humiliation spawns humiliation, and it can strike
deep. The dignity/humiliation framework seems to reach into the very core of
human conduct.
Defining Social
Integration
Apart from providing a perspective on social
inequality at the micro-level, Fuller’s approach also implies a unique path
into the study of social integration. Feeling like a ‘Somebody’ or a ‘Nobody’
can be used as a subjective indicator. The ‘Somebody’ feeling can be taken as a
signal of mutual acceptance, having an identity that is fully accepted by the
other(s). A complication in the path toward solidarity will be discussed below.
The ‘Nobody’ feeling, however, can be taken as a direct signal of alienation,
of feeling rejected by the other(s). This usage might be a preliminary step
toward clarifying the concept of social integration.
There is a difficulty in
seeing solidarity/alienation as a simple dichotomy that Fuller does not address
directly, yet his idea of rankism provides for it. Many authors have noted that
mutual acceptance occurs in two different forms, one of which is not true
solidarity.
There is a form of mutual
acceptance that is sometimes referred to as solidarity, but has only its
outward appearance. This form involves one or both parties giving up vital
parts of their own identity in order to be completely loyal to the
relationship. The traditional marriage is an example; the wife subordinates her
own needs and views to those of her husband. In family systems theory (Bowen
and Kerr 1988), this type of relationship is referred to as a fused or engulfed bond. The opposite relationship, in which one party
subordinates the needs of the other(s) to their own, is termed isolated. In a secure bond, both parties give equal value to their own needs and
views and those of the other, over the long haul. Norbert Elias (1987) made the
same division: he called solidarity “interdependence,” being neither dependent
(engulfed) nor independent (isolated). Note that the concept of engulfment
further develops the idea of alienation from self that Karl Marx mentioned
without explaining what he meant.
Fuller’s idea of rankism is
relevant to the issue of engulfment as a false solidarity. All forms of mutual
acceptance that are based on rankism, the arbitrary disparagement of another person
or group, are not forms of true solidarity, but engulfment. Mutual acceptance
of whites because they are not black, or gentiles because they are not Jews, of
males because they are not women, are all instances or rankism and therefore of
false solidarity.
The distinction between
isolation and engulfment suggests that alienation occurs in two opposite forms:
alienation from others (isolation) and from self (engulfment). This idea also requires
that a secure bond (solidarity) maintains a long-term balance between self and
other: one identifies with the needs and viewpoint of the other(s) as much as with
self, no less and no more. Genuine love can be defined as a type of solidarity
(see Scheff 2006, Chapter 6). The late Robert Solomon wrote:
Love [is] shared identity, a redefinition of self … Two
people in a society with an extraordinary sense of individual identity [find]
their way into a relationship that can no longer be understood as a mere
conjunction of the two but only as a complex ONE (Solomon 1981:xxx; see also Solomon 1994:234-238).
This kind of definition of love has been offered by
many authors, but like Solomon, they usually fail to include the balance
between too far (isolation) and too close (engulfment) as explained above. An
exception was the social psychiatrist Harry S. Sullivan (1945) who suggested
that love involves valuing the other as much as self, but neither more or less.
It is important to
distinguish between true and false solidarity, since both social science and ordinary
language often confound them. Most Western scholarship that compares Asian and
Western societies have idealized Western isolation and individualism by
confounding it with solidarity based on rational outcomes (e.g. Émile Durkheim’s
description of organic solidarity), as Hazel Rose Markus and Shinobu Kitayama
(1991) have charged. But it seems likely that they have made an equal and
opposite error, idealized Asian (unity-based) societies by confounding
engulfment with solidarity. Robin Norwood’s (1985) women who loved too much
provide an example of engulfment. Many of them reported that they stayed with
their abusive husbands because they loved them too much to leave. Their
language confuses engulfment, in this case, passive dependency, with genuine
love, a true solidarity. Fuller’s approach avoids this and many other problems
that will, however, not be touched upon here.
Conclusion
This chapter has reviewed Erving Goffman’s approach to
social psychology, pointing out its main strengths and weaknesses, with special
emphasis on his analysis of facework. Moreover, the chapter has delineated some
of the perspectives proposed by Robert W. Fuller who follows in the footsteps
of Goffman but also takes his ideas further. Fuller’s politics of dignity has
many advantages over Goffman’s analysis. It implies a new approach to defining
the poles of social integration: alienation and solidarity. It also suggests an
accessible theory of the origin of the causal chains that lead to inequalities
and to violence, both at the interpersonal and group levels. Unlike many
abstract social theories, Fuller’s is so clearly stated that it might help
resolve many theoretical knots, and can also be tested empirically. To the
extent that it is supported, it can be applied to solving real world problems.
Fuller’s work parallels
Goffman’s, but modifies and extends it in a way that might represent a major
step forward in social science. As the chapter has shown, Fuller’s writing
parallels Goffman’s on facework but it is clearer and broader. Goffman’s theses
are often unclear and claim to be narrowly limited to outer behavior in the
microworld of social interaction. Like Goffman, Fuller traces the emotional
consequences of losing face in humiliation/embarrassment, but unlike Goffman,
he gives equal consideration to dignity, that is, to justified pride. Also
unlike Goffman, Fuller’s work implies a step toward conceptualizing social
integration, the typology of solidarity and alienation. He proposes that rank
need not be alienating if rankism (the abuse of rank) is avoided. Fuller
applies these ideas to the macro problems of inequality and intractable
conflict. Further, and contrary to Goffman, he explores their application to
changing the real world. In many ways, Fuller can be seen as a new Goffman.
Bibliography
Blumer, Herbert.
1986. Symbolic
interactionism: perspective and method. Berkeley: University of
California Press.
Bowen, Murray and Michael E. Kerr (1988): Family Evaluation. New York: W. W. Norton & Company.
Cooley, Charles Horton (1902): Human Nature and the Social Order. New York: Scribner’s.
Elias, Norbert (1987): Involvement and Detachment. Oxford:
Blackwell.
Elias, Norbert. 1998. On Civilization, Knowledge, and Power: Selected Writings. Chicago:
University of Chicago Press.
Fuller, Robert W.
(2003): Somebodies and Nobodies. Gabriola Island: New Society Publishers.
Fuller, Robert W. (2006): All Rise. San Francisco,
CA: Berrett-Koehler Publishers.
Fuller, Robert W. and Pamela A. Gerloff (2008): Dignity for All. San
Francisco, CA: Berrett-Koehler
Publishers.
Goffman, Erving (1956): “Embarrassment and Social
Organization”. American Journal of Sociology,
62:264-274.
Goffman, Erving (1959): The Presentation of Self in Everyday Life. Garden City, NY: Doubleday/Anchor
Books.
Goffman, Erving (1961): Asylums. New York:
Anchor Books.
Goffman,
Erving. (1961a). Fun in games. In Encounters: Two studies in the sociology
of interaction, pp. 15–81. Indianapolis:
Bobbs-Merrill.
Goffman, Erving
(1967): Interaction Ritual: Essays on
Face-to-Face Behavior. New York:
Pantheon Books.
Goffman, Erving (1979): Gender Advertisements. London:
Macmillan.
Koestler, Arthur. 1967. The Action of
Creation. London: Hutcheson.
Leys, Simon (1998): “The Imitation of Our Lord Don
Quixote”. New York Review of Books,
45 (10), June 11, p. 32-36.
Lindner, Evelin G. (2006): Making Enemies: Humiliation in International Conflict. Portsmouth, NH:
Green Wood.
Lofland, John (1980): “Early Goffman: Style, Structure,
Substance, Soul”, in Jason Ditton (ed.): The
View from Goffman. New York: St. Martin’s Press.
Mead, G. H.
1936. Mind, Self, and Society.
Chicago: U. of Chicago Press
Mannheim, Karl (1951): Man and Society in an Age of Reconstruction: Studies in Modern Social Structure.
New York:
Harcourt Brace.
Manning, Peter K. (1980): “Goffman’s Framing Order:
Style as Structure”, in Jason Ditton (ed.): The
View from Goffman. New York: St. Martin’s Press.
Markus, Hazel Rose and Shinobu Kitayama (1991): “Culture
and the Self: Implications for Cognition, Emotion and Motivation”. Psychological
Review, 98
(2):224-253.
Norwood, Robin (1985): Women Who Love Too
Much. New York:
Pocket Books.
Oats, Joyce Carol (1974): New Heaven, New Earth. New
York: Vanguard Press.
Scheff, Thomas J. (1994): Bloody Revenge: Emotions, Nationalism and War. Boulder, CO:
Westview Press (re-issued in 1999 by iUniverse).
Scheff, Thomas J. (2000): “Shame and the Social Bond”.
Sociological Theory, 18:84-98.
Scheff, Thomas J. (2005): “Looking-Glass Self: Goffman
as Symbolic Interactionist”. Symbolic
Interaction, 28 (2):147-166.
Scheff, Thomas J. (2006): Goffman Unbound: A New Paradigm for Social Science. Boulder, CO:
Paradigm Publishers.
Solomon, Robert (1981): Love: Emotion, Myth, and Metaphor. Garden City, NY: Doubleday/Anchor
Books.
Solomon, Robert (1994): About Love: Re-Inventing Romance for Our Times. Lanham, MD:
Littlefield Adams.
Sullivan, Harry S. (1945): Conceptions of Modern Psychiatry. Washington, DC.: W. A. White
Foundation.
Whitehead,
Alfred. 1962. Science and the Modern World. New York: MacMillan.